アリストテレスの弁証術におけるτο τι ην ειναι (本質)
スポンサーリンク
概要
- 論文の詳細を見る
I offer an interpretation of the origin of how and why the phrase το τι ην ειναι (hereafter essence) is employed, by giving an account of the context in which essence is introduced and its linguistic structure. In "The Topics" Aristotle develops a method by means of which one can formally examine whether any proposed proposition is well said or not. This method of establishing and rejecting any proposition is developed as Topos theory. Topos is the locution of argument or the point at issue on the basis of which a questioner examines a proposition proposed by the counterpart of dialogue i. e. an answerer. Aristotle must have thought that Socratic dialectic is ad hoc as a method in the sense that his inquiry into definition by examining another's thesis always comes to a dead-end. Aristotle criticizes Socratic dialogue as follows ; "it was natural that Socrates should be seeking the essence,--there was as yet none of the dialectical power which enables people even without the "what is it?" to speculate about contraries"(1078b23-26). I take it that Aristotle strengthens dialectic by creating a system of inquiry into "what it is" and to deal with contraries without directly asking the question "what is it?". Dialectic argument must not raise the problem by asking the question "what is it?", but raise it like "whether is two-footed terrestrial animal the definition of man or not?" so as to be answered by just saying "yes or no"(101b32, 158a16). The main ingredients of Topos theory are four predicables (definition, unique property, genus and accident) of which every proposition is composed. Predicables are the ways of predicate's belonging to its subject. While "definition is a phrase which signifies essence", "unique property is what does not refer essence for some subject but belongs only to it and counterpredicates with it"(101b38, 102a18). In this way, any proposed proposition is classified into one of these four predicables. Since these four predicables are exclusive of one another, the reference of essence is fixed with respect to other three predicables and introduced as a technical phrase in the introduction of predicables. One common feature among these is that "all these are definitory"(102b34). Even accident is alleged to be regarded as "definitory", because nothing prevents it from temporarily "becoming unique property", a kind of identity which is the necessary condition for definition(102b21f, cf. 102a7-10). I claim that these four predicables are proposed to deal with all possible answers of the Socratic question "what is it?". An important characteristic in the Socratic practice of inquiring into definition is that he rejects the kind of answers which are given by examples i. e. accidents and asks again the object itself. For example, Socrates asks "what do you think knowledge is?". Theaetetus answers by giving examples of knowledge such as geometry. Socrates responds to this by saying "We put the question, not because we wanted to count them, but because we wanted to know what, exactly, knowledge itself is"(Theae., 146c-e, cf. Euth., 6d, Laches, 190e). This shows that the question "what is it?" in the Greek language can be answered by being given an example and also by an object itself. I claim that το τι ην ειναι is coined by Aristotle to convey the object itself so as to avoid confusions which took place between Socrates who has only one way of asking i. e. "τι εστι;" and the answerer. If this interpretation is right, the linguistic structure of essence will be made clear. I will just focus on the reason why the imperfect ην is employed. Goodwin writes in his Syntax of Greek Moods and Tenses that "The imperfect ην may express a fact which is just recognized as such by the speaker or writer, having previously been denied, overlooked, or not understood" (13). I call this use of ην "dialectical imperfect". This use accords very well with the dialectical situation where the question of the thing itself is asked afresh : When an example is given as an answer, the questioner, recognizing what is overlooked and misunderstood, asks again what the thing itself is. Thus, Aristotle develops the method of dialectic as Topos theory on the basis of predicables. The normativeness of Topos theory is gained from the normativeness of the current language in the Academy. Division theory on the basis of inductive method is its main current language. Essence is signified by the definition composed of genus and its difference. Essence is properly λογικω&b.sigmav; discussed. Λογικω&b.sigmav; is the method of linguistic inquiry from the view point of "how to express" which can claim an assertion of being on the basis of necessity of argument. Essence is λογικω&b.sigmav; characterized as "to be the very thing what is" which may be tautologous but claims a mode of being i. e. the object itself(141a35, cf. 73b8, 1030a3). In this way, essence is introduced in the dialectical context to express what Socrates sought for in his inquiry into definition.
- 日本西洋古典学会の論文
- 1999-03-23
著者
関連論文
- アリストテレスの弁証術における言語哲学 : 本質、定義形成句そして意味表示の二重機能
- パウロ「ローマ書」の言語哲学 : 神学論争の解消に向けて
- パウロ「ローマ書」の言語哲学--神学論争の解消に向けて
- 坂下浩司, 『アリストテレスの形而上学-自然学と倫理学の基礎』, Pp.190, 岩波書店, 2002年, 7600円+税.
- 基体と質料 : アリストテレス『形而上学』Z3研究
- 序説 信の哲学 : ギリシア哲学者使途パウロ (中)
- 序説 信の哲学 : ギリシア哲学者使途パウロ (上)
- Aristotle's Theory of Definition in Posterior Analytics B. 10
- 存在と恩寵 : 自己の一性と差異をめぐって
- パウロ『ローマ書』の構成と試訳
- 多元的価値の共存可能性 : ヨーロッパ文化の源流をたずねて
- トマスとルターにおける信仰と愛 : 徳と恩寵の両立可能性
- トマスとルターにおける信仰と愛--徳と恩寵の両立可能性
- アリストテレスにおける力と運動 : 可能態、完全現実態そして現実活動態
- 研究発表要旨 信仰と愛--ルターによるパリ学派批判を手掛かりに
- 信仰義認論と愛--人間存在の新しい可能性 (シンポジウム-愛)
- 書評 土屋博『教典になった宗教』北海道大学図書刊行会
- アリストテレス哲学における方法論 : ロギケー(形式言論構築術)の展開
- 『ロマ書』におけるパウロの意味論
- アリストテレス『分析論後書』における論証と定義 : アカデメイアにおける探究論の文脈
- アリストテレス『分析論後書』における論証と定義--アカデメイアにおける探究論の文脈
- アリストテレスにおける本質(το τί ην ειναι)の非因果論的解釈 : その使用の文脈と言語分析を手掛かりに
- アリストテレスの弁証術におけるτο τι ην ειναι (本質)
- ペラギウス論争とその調停者パウロ
- オープンキャンパス体験講義 「人間の学としての哲学 : 東日本大震災への一教員からのメッセージ」 Vision : 心魂と科学技術文明の再定位
- アリストテレスにおける発見的探究と何であるかの論証
- アリストテレス哲学における方法論 -形而上学の可能性を開くもの-
- アリストテレスの本質主義--必然性の源泉としての本質
- 科学技術と人間--21世紀のライフスタイル一考
- アリストテレスの心身論のパズルと質料形相論
- ***-スとアガペ---ヘレニズムとヘブライズムの絆
- アリストテレス「自然学」II9における目的と必然性
- アリストテレスの目的論的自然観-2-
- アリストテレスの目的論的自然観-1-
- アリストテレスの存在論的倫理学--紹介と批評:David Charles Aristotle′s Philosophy of Action 1984
- 「オッカムの言語哲学」清水哲郎
- アリストテレス「分析論後書」における発見的探究論と論証