アリストテレス「自然学」II9における目的と必然性
スポンサーリンク
概要
- 論文の詳細を見る
I offer an interpretation, mainly on the basis of Physics II 9, of Aristotle's claim in his biological writings that explanation by necessity involving only material and efficient causes is consistent with an explanation of the same phenomena by purpose. My argument is directed towards the further question of whether Aristotle also believes that while the essences of certain biological phenomena are partly determined by their role in a teleological system, there is a complete account in terms of material and efficient causation of the conditions under which they exist. Physics II 9 presupposes his argument for the final cause as the nature in the primary sense in II 8, and is similar in theme to Parts of Animals 1 1 where Aristotle criticises the physiologoi on the ground that when they claimed that biological phenomena come into being by necessity, they fail to distinguish what kind of necessity is involved. At the beginning of II 9, Aristotle considers two alternative ways of understanding the necessity involved in generation ; either hypothetical necessity(HN) or HN plus simple necessity(SN). HN depends on a goal. If the goal is to be, it is necessary that certain other things come to be. SN, by contrast, depends on the nature of simple bodies and their movements. Aristotle locates the SN which the physiologoi take as the main cause of generation as a "necessary nature" (200a8) and regards this as explanatory of the goal, only insofar as the latter is purely materially specified as the matter of the goal(ω&b.sigmav; δι υλην). The goal taken as its matter is simply necessitated by its material components in the sense that the material components yield a specified condition for the existence of the goal. Thus Aristotle expresses two modes of necessity involved in generation as follows ; "The necessity, then, is on a hypothesis, but isn't necessary as the same way the goal(ω&b.sigmav; τελο&b.sigmav;) is necessary. For in the latter case the necessity lies in the matter, but in the former case the purpose lies in the λογο&b.sigmav; (account as design)." (200a13ff) Aristotle confirms the two modes of necessity in comparison with a mathematical reasoning. He compares both (1) "things which come to be based on nature(κατα <φυσιν)"(200a16) and (2) "things which come to be for something" (al9) with the necessity involved in a specific mathematical proof : given that the straight is thus and so, necessarily the triangle has angles whose sum is two right angles. While (1) is wider than (2) in terms of their extensions, they differ from each other in that the necessity involved in (1) is determined by the nature of underlying(υποκειμενομ), but the necessity involved in (2) is determined by goal. Aristotle defines nature in "κατα φυσιν" in (1) as a certain underlying based on simple bodies which have "natural tendency for change" (ορμη 192b18 cf. 95 al, 276a26) for both "substances" which "have a nature"(192b33) as formal or final cause and "their per se components" (cf. 73a34ff)which "do not have a nature" (193 a1) specified above as moving upwards belongs to fire. In that mathematical reasoning, the premises or components of the conclusion determine the necessity of the conclusion. This is said to be "in a parallel fashion" (200a16) with the case in (1). On the other hand, it is said to be "in a reversed fashion"(a19) with case in (2) in the sense that the goal which is achieved at the end of generation determines the necessity of the antecedent which comes no doubt earlier than the end. In this way, these two modes of necessity in generation are indirectly compared with each other via an example of mathematics. I conclude that while the purpose as design at the level of Adyoc determines what kind of matter should be employed in generation "as matter of λογο&b.sigmav; (200b8) , matter at the level of generation necessarily generates the matter of a goal by its own power, according to the program which is laid as design at the level of λογο&b.sigmav;. This allows us to say eg. eyeball and optic nerve etc. are an eye by themselves for the sake of seeing(cf. 1041a26). By distinguishing the level of λογο&b.sigmav; in which the purpose lies from the level of generation in which material necessity lies, Aristotle sets up the compatibility between teleological explanation of biological phenomena and explanation by material necessity in which both HN and SN lie.
- 日本西洋古典学会の論文
- 1994-03-28
著者
関連論文
- アリストテレスの弁証術における言語哲学 : 本質、定義形成句そして意味表示の二重機能
- パウロ「ローマ書」の言語哲学 : 神学論争の解消に向けて
- 坂下浩司, 『アリストテレスの形而上学-自然学と倫理学の基礎』, Pp.190, 岩波書店, 2002年, 7600円+税.
- 基体と質料 : アリストテレス『形而上学』Z3研究
- 序説 信の哲学 : ギリシア哲学者使途パウロ (中)
- 序説 信の哲学 : ギリシア哲学者使途パウロ (上)
- Aristotle's Theory of Definition in Posterior Analytics B. 10
- 存在と恩寵 : 自己の一性と差異をめぐって
- パウロ『ローマ書』の構成と試訳
- 多元的価値の共存可能性 : ヨーロッパ文化の源流をたずねて
- トマスとルターにおける信仰と愛 : 徳と恩寵の両立可能性
- トマスとルターにおける信仰と愛--徳と恩寵の両立可能性
- アリストテレスにおける力と運動 : 可能態、完全現実態そして現実活動態
- 研究発表要旨 信仰と愛--ルターによるパリ学派批判を手掛かりに
- 信仰義認論と愛--人間存在の新しい可能性 (シンポジウム-愛)
- 書評 土屋博『教典になった宗教』北海道大学図書刊行会
- アリストテレス哲学における方法論 : ロギケー(形式言論構築術)の展開
- 『ロマ書』におけるパウロの意味論
- アリストテレス『分析論後書』における論証と定義 : アカデメイアにおける探究論の文脈
- アリストテレス『分析論後書』における論証と定義--アカデメイアにおける探究論の文脈
- アリストテレスにおける本質(το τί ην ειναι)の非因果論的解釈 : その使用の文脈と言語分析を手掛かりに
- アリストテレスの弁証術におけるτο τι ην ειναι (本質)
- ペラギウス論争とその調停者パウロ
- オープンキャンパス体験講義 「人間の学としての哲学 : 東日本大震災への一教員からのメッセージ」 Vision : 心魂と科学技術文明の再定位
- アリストテレスにおける発見的探究と何であるかの論証
- アリストテレス哲学における方法論 -形而上学の可能性を開くもの-
- アリストテレスの本質主義--必然性の源泉としての本質
- 科学技術と人間--21世紀のライフスタイル一考
- アリストテレスの心身論のパズルと質料形相論
- ***-スとアガペ---ヘレニズムとヘブライズムの絆
- アリストテレス「自然学」II9における目的と必然性
- アリストテレスの目的論的自然観-2-
- アリストテレスの目的論的自然観-1-
- アリストテレスの存在論的倫理学--紹介と批評:David Charles Aristotle′s Philosophy of Action 1984
- 「オッカムの言語哲学」清水哲郎
- アリストテレス「分析論後書」における発見的探究論と論証